A History of
Islamic Philosophy
Second Edition
Majid Fakhry
Columbia University Press, New York
1983
Contents
Chapter One. The Legacy of Greece, Alexandria, and the Orient
I.
The Near Eastern Scene in the Seventh Century
II.
The Translations of Philosophical Texts
III.
Neo-Platonic Elements: The Apocryphal Theologia
Aristotelis and the Liber de Causis
IV.
Persian and Indian Influences
Chapter Two. Early Political and Religious Tensions
I.
The Religio-Political Factions
II.
The Rise of Islamic Scholasticism (Kalam)
Chapter Three. Beginnings of Systematic Philosophical Writing in the
Ninth Century
I.
The First Creative Philosophical Writer in Islam: Al-Kindi
II.
The Rise of Naturalism and the Challenge to Islamic Dogma: Ibn Al-Rawandi and
Al-Razi
Chapter Four. The Further development of Islamic Neo-Platonism
I.
Al-Farabi
II.
Ibn Sina
Chapter Five. Neo-Pythagoreanism and the Popluarization of the
Philosophical Sciences.
I.
Philosophy, the handmaiden of Politics
II.
The Mathematico-Philosophical Presuppositions of the Brethren
III.
The Cosmology and Metaphysics of the Brethren
IV.
The Psychology and the Epistemology of the
Brethren
V.
Conclusion
Chapter Six. The Diffusion of the Philosophical culture in the Tenth
Century
I.
Abu Hayyan Al-Tauhidi
II.
Miskawayh
III.
Yahia b. ‘Adi
II.
The Ash’arite school and the Formulation of the Occasionalist
Metaphysics of Atoms and accidents
Chapter eight. The Rise and Development of Islamic Mysticism (Sufism)
I.
Ascetic Origins
II.
Pantheistic Tendencies: Al-Bastami (or Al-Bistami), Al-Hallaj, and others
III.
Synthesis and Systematization – Al-Ghazali and Ibn ‘Arabi
Chapter Nine. The Arab-Spanish Interlude and the Revival of
Perpateticism
I.
Beginnings of Philosophical Speculation in Muslim Spain: Ibn Masarrah, Al-Majriti,
and Ibn Bajjah
II.
Ibn Tufayl and the Natural Progression of the Mind Toward Truth
III.
Ibn Rushd and the Defense of Aristotelianism
Chapter Ten. Post-Avicennian Developments: Illumination
and the Reaction against Peripateticism
I.
Al-Suhrawardi
II.
The Subsequent Development of Illumination: Sadr Al-Din Al-Shirazi (Mulla Sadra)
and his successors
Chapter Eleven. Theological Reaction and Reconstruction
I.
Literalism and Neo-Hanbalism: Ibn Hazm, Ibn Taymiyah, and Muhammad B.
‘Abdul-Wahhab
II.
Moderation and Decline: F. D. Al-Razi, N. D. Al-Nasafi, Al-Iji, Al-Jurjani and
Al-Bajuri
III.
Reaction and Reconstruction: Ibn Khaldun
Chapter Twelve. Modern Contemporary Trends
I.
The Emergence of the Modernist Spirit: J. D. Al-Afghani, Muhammad ‘Abdu
II.
Modernism in India: Sayyid Ahmad Khan, Ameer Ali, and Muhammad Iqbal
III.
Contemporary Philosophical Scene: Fundamentalism, Modernism, and Existentialism
IV.
Other Recent Developments: Positivism and Socialism
Bibliography
Preface to the First Edition
The interest of Western scholars in the development of
Islamic philosophical thought has been comparatively small. There appear to be two reasons
for this neglect: the nature of the subject matter and the character of Western
scholarship itself. The main body of Islamic thought, in so far as it has any relevance
outside the scope of Islam, belongs to a remote past. In fact, as this book will show,
Islamic philosophy is and continues to be, even in the twentieth century, fundamentally
medieval in spirit and outlook. Consequently,
from the time of Thomas Aquinas and Roger Bacon until now, interest in this thought has
been cultivated in the West only in so far as it could be shown to have a direct or
indirect bearing on the development of European philosophy or Christian theology. More
recently, attempts have been made by Western scholars to break away from this pattern and
to approach Islamic philosophy as an intellectual concern in its own right, but the fruits
of these efforts remain meager compared to the work of scholars in such cognate fields as
the political, economic, and social development of the Muslim peoples.
Second, we note the radically modern direction that
philosophy has taken in the West, from the seventeenth century on. Fresh attempts are
continually being made to formulate a coherent world view for modern man, in which the
role of ancient (Greek) and medieval (both Arabic and Latin) thought is progressively
ignored or minimized. In this way Islamic philosophy suffers the same fate as European
medieval philosophy. Furthermore, the role that Arabic philosophy played in preserving and
transmitting Greek thought between A.D. 800 and 1200 has become much less significant for
Western scholarship since the recovery of the original Greek texts.
It can hardly be denied that the system of ideas by which the
Muslim peoples have interpreted and continue to interpret the world is relevant to the
student of culture. Nor is the more abstract, formulation of this system, in theology or
metaphysics, devoid of, intrinsic value. For it should be recalled that Greek philosophy,
in which modern Western thought has its origins, has played a crucial role in the
formulation of Islamic philosophy, whereas it has made almost no impact on other cultures,
such as the Indian or Chinese. This consideration alone should be sufficient to reveal the
close affinities between Islamic and Western thought.
The first important modern study in the general field of
Arabic philosophy is Amable Jourdain’s Recherches
critiques sur l’âge et l’origine des traductions d’Aristote et sur Ies
documents grecs ou arabes employés par Ies docteurs scholastiques, which appeared in
1819. This book helped to underscore the influence of Arabic philosophy on Western,
particularly Latin, scholastic thought. It was followed in 1852 by Ernest Rénan’s
classic study, Averroês et I’averroïsme,
which has since been reprinted several times. In 1859 appeared Solomon Munk’s Mélanges de philosophie juive et arabe, a general
survey of Jewish-Arabic philosophy which is still of definite value. Early in the
twentieth century appeared T. J. de Boer’s Geschichte
der Philosophie in Islam (1901), which was translated into English in 1903 and
continues to be the best comprehensive account of Islamic philosophy in German and
English. A more popular but still useful survey, Arabic
Thought and Its Place in History by de Lacy O’Leary, appeared in 1922. The many
surveys by Carra de Vaux, G. Quadri, and L. Gauthier are listed in the Bibliography.
We must mention, however, three historical narratives which
appeared in very recent years. M. Cruz Hernandez, Filosofia
hispano-musulmana (1957), though primarily concerned with Spanish-Muslim philosophy,
contains extensive and valuable accounts of the major “Eastern” philosophers and
schools. W. Montgomery Watt’s Islamic
Philosophy and Theology (1962), which is part of a series entitled “Islamic
Surveys,” is weighted in favor of theology and therefore does not add much to our
knowledge of Islamic philosophy. Henry Corbin’s Histoire
de la philosophie islamique (1964), though very valuable, does not recognize the
organic character of Islamic thought and tends to overemphasize the Shi’ite and
particularly Isma’ili element in the history of this thought. M. M. Sharif’s History of Muslim Philosophy is a symposium by a
score of writers and lacks for this reason the unity of conception and plan that should
characterize a genuine historical survey.
In the field of Greco-Arab scholarship, Islamic philosophy
owes much to the studies of Richard Walzer, now available in the one-volume Greek into Arabic (1962), and to the critical
editions of texts prepared by M. Bouyges, S.J. (d. 1951) and ‘Abdu’l-Rahman
Badawi. Bouyges made available to scholars, in the Bibliotheca
Arabica Scholasticorum, a series of fundamental works in unsurpassed critical
editions. A. R. Badawi has edited, over a period of two decades, a vast amount of
philosophical texts which have considerably widened the scope of Arabic philosophical
studies. As for the Ishraqi tradition, Henry Corbin is a pioneer whose studies will
probably acquire greater signif1cance as the post-Averroist and Shi‘ite element in
Muslim philosophy is more fully appreciated. Finally, the studies of L. Gardet, Mlle. A.
M. Goichon, L. Gauthier, I. Madkour, S. van den Bergh, G. C. Anawati, S. Pines, M. Alonso.
and L. Massignon are among the most important contemporary contributions to the study of
Muslim thought; these books are listed in the Bibliography.
An argument against the attempt to write a general history of
Islamic philosophy might be based on the fact that a great deal of the material involved
must await critical editions and analysis before an attempt can be made to assess it. I
believe that this objection is valid in principle. However, a fair amount of material is
now available, either in good editions or manuscripts, and the collation of the two should
make interpretation relatively accurate. More over, the writing of a general history that
would give scholars a comprehensive view of the whole field is a prerequisite of progress
in that field, since it is not possible otherwise to determine the areas in which further
research must be pursued or the gaps which must be filled.
We might finally note that the writing of a history of
philosophy, as distinct from a philosophical chronicle, must involve a considerable
element of interpretation and evaluation, in addition to the bare narrative of events, the
listing of authors, or the exposition of concepts; without such interpretation the dynamic
movement of the mind, in its endeavor to comprehend the world in a coherent manner, can
scarcely be understood. In taking this approach a writer might find it valuable to
reexamine areas which others have studied before him. In this hazardous undertaking I have
naturally tried to learn as much as possible from other scholars. However, in the
exposition of philosophical concepts or problems I have relied primarily on the writings
of the philosophers themselves. Sometimes the interpretation of philosophical or
theological doctrines has compelled me to turn to the studies of contemporary authorities.
I did not feel, however, once those doctrines had been sufficiently clarified, that it was
necessary to multiply these authorities endlessly. The purpose of the Bibliography at the
end of the book is to acquaint the interested reader with the work of other scholars in
the field and to indicate the extent of the material used in the writing of this book.
I wish to acknowledge my debt to the many persons and
institutions that have made the publication of this work possible. In particular, I thank
the librarians at Istanbul, Oxford, the Escorial, Paris, London, the Vatican, and the
Library of Congress who have generously given their assistance. To the Research Committee
and the Arabic Studies Program of the American University of Beirut I am particularly
indebted for financing the research and travel that I did in connection with writing large
parts of this book. To the Publications Committee of this University I am indebted for a
generous subsidy to meet the editorial costs of preparing the manuscript for press. I also
wish to thank the former Dean of the School Arts and Sciences of the American University
of Beirut, Professor Farid S. Hanania, for his encouragement in the early stages of
writing the book, and Professors Arthur Sewell and David Curnow for their help in editing
the manuscript, at least up to Chapter Seven. And to the many unnamed scholars and
colleagues, from whose advice and criticism I have profited more than I can say, I extend
a warm expression of thanks. Finally to Georgetown University I am grateful for assistance
in the final preparation of the manuscript and the opportunity, while engaged in teaching,
to complete the last chapters of this book, and to the staff of Columbia University Press
for their courtesy and efficiency in producing this volume.
Majid Fakhry
Preface to the Second Edition
The
present edition of this History of Islamic
Philosophy, which was first published in 1970, embodies a number of changes which I
hope will make this book even more useful to the reader than the first one. A number of
corrections have been made throughout the book, the final chapter expanded somewhat and
the bibliography updated and rearranged.
An author has a moral obligation to acknowledge his debt both
to those who praise and those who criticize his work, in so far as he can learn from both.
I was particularly gratified, when this book first appeared, by the warm reception it met
in certain academic quarters and the favorable reviews it was given by a number of
distinguished scholars, some of whom I knew personally and some I did not. On the other
hand, I was not unduly disturbed at the far fewer criticisms or denigrations.
Perhaps it is necessary to state in conclusion that, while I
am fully aware of the shortcomings of the present book, I continue, after more than ten
years of study and reflection, and despite certain criticisms, to stick to the overall
thematic and historiographical schema originally adopted in writing it.
Majid Fakhry
NOTE ON TRANSLATION OF ARABIC PASSAGES. Unless otherwise
indicated, the translation of Arabic excerpts is the work of the author. The system of
transliteration of Arabic terms and proper names adopted in this book is, with slight
modifications, that of the Encyclopaedia of Islam.
Introduction
Islamic
philosophy is the product of a complex intellectual process in which Syrians, Arabs,
Persians, Turks, Berbers, and others took an active part. The Arab element is so
preponderant, however, that it might be conveniently termed Arabic philosophy. The medium
in which writers, hailing from such distant countries as Khurasan and Andalusia, chose to
express their thoughts from the eighth to the seventeenth centuries was Arabic. The racial
element that provided the cohesive force in this cosmopolitan endeavor and determined its
form and direction, at least in the early stages, was Arabic; without the Arabs’
enlightened interest in ancient learning, hardly any intellectual progress could have been
made or maintained. Moreover, it was the Arabs who, while they assimilated the customs,
manners, and learning of their subject peoples, contributed the one universal element in
the whole complex of Muslim culture, i.e., the Islamic religion.
As we proceed we shall note the role of each racial group in
the development of Islamic philosophy. We observe here that the intellectual history of
the Arabs, to whom the development of philosophy and science in the Near East owed so
much, virtually begins with the rise of Islam. The chief cultural monuments of the Arabs,
before the rise of Islam, were poetry and literary traditions that were transmitted orally
and embody a record of the social, political, religious, and moral aspects of Arab life.
However, this record was primitive, regional, and fragmentary. Islam not only provided the
Arabs with a coherent and bold world-view, which sought to transcend the narrow confines
of their tribal existence, but thrust them almost forcibly upon the cultural stage of the
ancient world and set before them its dazzling scientific and cultural treasures.
The pivot round which the whole of Muslim life turns is, of
course, the Qur’an. Revealed to Muhammad by God between 610 and 632 from an eternal
codex (the Preserved Tablet), according to Muslim doctrine, the Qur’an embodies the
full range of principles and precepts by which the believer should order his life. The
Qur’an is supplemented, however, by a mass of utterances attributed to Muhammad and
constituting, together with circumstantial reports of the actions and decisions of the
Prophet, the general body of Muhammadan Traditions, properly designated in Muslim usage as
the Prophetic “Way” (al-Sunnah).
Overwhelmed by the awesome sacredness of the divine Word
(kalam) and the Prophetic Way, the first generation of Muslim scholars dedicated
themselves wholly to the fixing of the sacred canon, commenting upon it and drawing the
legal or moral corollaries implicit in it. Thus arose the sciences of reading (‘ilm al-qira’at), exegesis (tafsir), and jurisprudence (fiqh), the only basic sciences the nascent
community needed in order to assimilate or live by the divinely revealed ordinances of the
Qur’an. From these sciences, however, there soon stemmed the whole body of subsidiary
disciplines, collectively referred to as the linguistic or traditional sciences, as
distinct from the rational or philosophical sciences.[1] Grammar, rhetoric, and the allied studies were developed
during the first two centuries of the Muslim era, chiefly as a means of adequately
interpreting or justifying the linguistic usages of the Qur’an and the Traditions.
Even study of literature, and particularly pre-Islamic poetry, appears to have been
stimulated by the desire to find a venerable basis in ancient usage for the many
unfamiliar terms or idioms in the Qur’an and the Traditions.
The canonical text of the Qur’an was finally fixed
during the reign of the third caliph, Uthman (644-656), and in honor of him the authorized
version of the Qur’an ever since has been called “Musaf Uthman”.[2] A few minor refinements of a purely grammatical and
orthographic nature were made in the tenth century. The Traditions, on the other hand,
circulated orally for almost two centuries, and in consequence a vast amount of apocryphal
material was added to what must have been the original core. By the middle of the ninth
century, however, elaborate criteria for sifting this material were developed and
compilations of “sound” or canonical Traditions were made, the best known and
most authoritative of which is that of al-Bukhari (d. 870).[3]
As one might expect, the greatest scholars of the early
period were primarily linguists or exegetes who addressed themselves to the study and
analysis of the texts of the Qur’an and the Traditions, on the one hand, or the
interpretation of the juridical aspects of Scripture and their application to concrete
cases, on the other. The first function was discharged by the commentators and
Traditionists, and the second by the jurisconsults (fuqaha’),
upon whom also devolved, in the absence of an organized teaching authority in Islam, the
task of doctrinal definition as well.
The criteria for settling juridical or even doctrinal
problems by the early jurisconsults were often purely linguistic or textual. However,
there soon arose a class of scholars who were willing to permit the use of analogy (qiyas) or independent judgment (ra’y) in
doubtful matters, especially when a specific textual basis for a decision could not be
found in Scripture. Of the four major legal schools into which Muslim jurisprudence
eventually crystallized, the school of Abu Hanifah (d. 767) and that of al-Shafi’i
(d. 820) were much more liberal than the two rival schools of Malik b. Anas (d. 795) and
Ahmad b. Hanbal (d. 855).
The implications of this bipolarity for the subsequent
development of scholastic theology (Kalam) are
not far to seek. The conservative “people of Tradition,” as the Malikites and
the Hanbalites are generally called, tended to repudiate the use of any deductive method.
Their position is best epitomized by the comment of Malik on the Qur’anic reference
to God’s “sitting upon the throne” (Qur’an 7:54 and 20:5). “The
sitting,” he is reported to have said, “is known, its modality is unknown.
Belief in it is an obligation and raising questions regarding it is a heresy
[bid‘ah].”4[4]
This somewhat narrow approach to the questions raised by the
study of Qur’anic texts could not long withstand the pressures of the times. There
was first the inevitable confrontation of Islam with paganism and Christianity, both at
Damascus and at Baghdad, and the numerous tensions it generated. Second, there were the
moral and legal questions raised by the gloomy picture of God’s overwhelming
supremacy in the world as depicted in the Qur’an, and its bearing on the
responsibility of human agents. And there was finally the necessity of safeguarding what
one may call the unity of the Islamic view of life, which could not be achieved without a
systematic attempt to bring the conflicting data of revelation (in the Qur’an and the
Traditions) into some internal harmony.
The attempt to grapple with these complex problems is at the
basis of the rise and development of Islamic scholastic theology. A good deal of the work
of the earliest theologians consisted in the rebuttal of the arguments leveled at Islam by
pagans, Christians, and Jews. Significantly, the early Mu‘tazilite doctors are often
commended for their defense of Islam against the attacks of the Materialists (al-Dahriyah) and the Manichaeans.[5] Indeed, heresiographers explicitly state that scholastic
theology arose as a means of buttressing Islamic beliefs by logical arguments and
defending them against attack.[6]
Within the confines of Islam itself, discussion began to
center by the seventh century around the questions of divine justice and human
responsibility. Authorities report that a cluster of early theologians engaged in the
discussion of the problem of free will and predestination (qadar), an issue generally recognized as the first
major one broached by the early theologians. The Mu‘tazilah, who continued this line
of speculation, asserted the freedom of the individual on the one hand and the justice of
God on the other. And although they naturally supported their positions by quotations from
the Qur’an, their general tendency was to advance arguments of a strictly ethical or
rational character in support of these positions.
Moreover, the anthropomorphic passages in which the
Qur’an abounded made it imperative to resort to some process of allegorical
interpretation in order to safeguard the immateriality and transcendence of God. Here
again the Mu‘tazilah were undoubted pioneers. The Qur’anic references to
God’s “sitting upon the throne,” as well as the possibility of seeing Him
on the Last Day,” (Qur’an 75:22, etc.), are interpreted as allegories for the
divine attributes of majesty or royalty on the one hand, or the possibility; of
contemplating Him mystically on the other.[7]
The proper prosecution of discussions of this kind naturally
called for a high degree of sophistication, which, prior to the introduction of Greek
philosophy and logic, was rather difficult, if not impossible. Scholastic theology
therefore gave the Muslims, as it had (given the Christians of Egypt and Syria centuries
earlier, the incentive to pursue the study of Greek philosophy.
Not much progress was made in that direction during the
Umayyad period (661-750). The Umayyad caliphs, especially during the first few decades of
their rule, were concerned primarily with the consolidation of their political power and
the solution of the numerous economic and administrative problems which governing a vast
empire raised.
However, souls thirsting after knowledge were not altogether
wanting even during this period. We might mention, as a striking instance, the Umayyad
prince Khalid b. Yazid (d. 704), who appears to have sought consolation in alchemy and
astrology for his disappointed claims to the caliphate. According to our most ancient
sources, Khalid provided for the first translations of scientific works (medical,
astrological, and alchemical) into Arabic. Nevertheless, the development of philosophy and
theology in Islam is bound up with the advent of the ‘Abbasid dynasty in the middle
of the eighth century. Interest in science and philosophy grew during this period to such
an extent that scientific and philosophical output was no longer a matter of individual
effort or initiative. Before long, the state took an active part in its promotion and the
intellectual repercussions of this activity acquired much greater scope. Theological
divisions, growing out of philosophical controversy or inquiry racked the whole of the
Muslim community. Caliphs upheld one theological view against another and demanded
adherence to it on political grounds, with the inevitable result that theology soon became
the handmaid of politics. As a consequence, freedom of thought and conscience was
seriously jeopardized.
A fundamental cause of this development is, of course, the
close correlation in Islam between principle and law, the realm of the temporal and the
realm of the spiritual. But such a development required the challenge of foreign ideas and
a release from the shackles of dogma. This is precisely the role played by the of Greek
ideas and the Greek spirit of intellectual curiosity, which generated a bipolar reaction
of the utmost importance for the understanding of Islam. The most radical division caused
by the introduction of Greek thought was between the progressive element, which sought
earnestly to subject the data of revelation to the scrutiny of philosophical thought, and
the conservative element, which disassociated itself altogether from philosophy on the
ground that it was either impious or suspiciously foreign. This division continued to
reappear throughout Islamic history as a kind of geological fault, sundering the whole of
Islam. As a result, throughout Muslim history reform movements have not been marked by a
great degree of release from authority or dogma or a quest for the reinterpretation or
reexamination of fundamental presuppositions in the realms of social organization,
theological discussion, or legal thought. Instead, like the reform of al-Ash‘ari (d.
935) in the tenth century, that of Ibn Taymiya (d. 1327) in the fourteenth century, or
that of Muhammad ‘Abdu (d. 1905) in the nineteenth century, they were marked by a
deliberate attempt to vindicate the old, Traditionist concepts and assumptions of the
earliest protagonists of Muslim dogma, the so-called good forebears, (al-salaf al-salih) of the Muslim community.
One lasting consequence of the introduction of Greek
philosophy and the Greek spirit of inquiry, however, was that the “Traditionism”
of early theologians and jurists, such as Malik b. Anas, was no longer tenable in its pure
or original form. The great Ash‘arite “reformers” committed, as they were
to the defense of orthodoxy against heretics and free thinkers, could no longer do so
without recourse to the weapons which their rationalist opponents had borrowed from the
Greeks. It was as though most of Greek dialectic could no longer be exorcised without
recourse to the formula of exorcism which it had itself enunciated in the first place.
Moreover, the, varying degrees of allegiance to Greek
philosophy and logic not only gave rise to the diverse theological schools of thought, but
generated the more distinctly, Hellenic current of ideas, which we shall designate as the
Islamic philosophical school.
The rise and development of this school is the primary
concern of the present history. Scholastic theology will be discussed only in so far as it
absorbed, reacted to, or by-passed Islamic philosophy. To theology might be added another
movement whose relation to philosophy has also fluctuated between the two poles of total
endorsement or total disavowal-mysticism or Sufism.
Mysticism is ultimately rooted in the original matrix of religious experience, which grows
in turn out of man’s overwhelming awareness of God and his sense of nothingness
without Him, and of the urgent need to subordinate reason and emotion to this experience.
The mystical experience, it is often claimed, is distinct from the rational or the
philosophical, and, less often, it is said to be contrary to it. But, whether it is
distinct or not, it can hardly be irrelevant to man’s rational or philosophical
aspirations; since it allegedly leads to the very object which reason seeks, namely, the
total and supreme apprehension of reality. In fact, the history of Muslim mysticism is more closely bound up with that of philosophy than
other forms of mysticism have been. The mysticism of some of the great Sufis such as Ibn ‘Arabi (d. 1240 ),
culminated in a grandiose cosmological and metaphysical world-scheme, which is of decisive
philosophical significance. Conversely, the philosophical preoccupations of some
philosophers, such as Ibn Bajjah (d. 1138) and Ibn Tufayl (d. 1185), led logically and
inevitably to the conception of mystical experience (designated “illumination”)
as the crowning of the process of reasoning.
The beginnings of the Islamic philosophical school coincide
with the first translations of the works of the Greek masters into Arabic from Syriac or
Greek. We might accept as credible the traditional account that scientific and medical
texts were the earliest works to be translated into Arabic. The Arabs, as well as the
Persians, who contributed so abundantly to the scientific and philosophical enlightenment
in Islam, are a practical-minded people. Their interest in the more abstract aspects of
Greek thought must have been a subsequent development. Even the Christian Syrians, who
paved the way for the introduction of the Greek heritage into the Near East shortly before
the Arab conquest in the seventh century, were interested primarily in Aristotelian logic
and Greek philosophy as a prelude to the study of theological texts. These were not only
written originally in Greek, but also were rich in logical and philosophical terms that
previously had been unknown to the Semites. In addition to scientific and medical works,
collections of moral aphorisms ascribed to Socrates, Solon, Hermes, Pythagoras, Luqman,
and similar real or fictitious personages appear to have been among the earliest texts to
be translated into Arabic. The Arab accounts of Greek philosophy abound in such apocryphal
literature, whose exact origin is sometimes difficult to ascertain. It might be assumed
that it was the affinity of these writings to belles lettres (adab) and their literary excellence which insured
their early vogue among the elite. Translators had naturally to depend upon the generosity
of their aristocratic or wealthy patrons, who, even when they affected interest in other
than the purely practical disciplines of astrology or medicine at all, were content with
this species of ethical and religious literature, which was cherished and disseminated
partly as a matter of social refinement and partly as a matter of moral edification.
Interest in the more abstract forms of ancient, especially Greek, learning was bound to
follow in due course, however. First, the translators themselves, having mastered skills
required for translating into Arabic more practical works, proceeded next to tackle works
of a greater speculative interest, and eventually to induce their patrons to provide for
their translation. Secondly, the theological controversies had reached such a point of
sophistication by the end of the eighth
century that the old weapons were no longer sufficient for the defense of orthodoxy, which
had now been given the authority of the state. Abstract philosophy was further popularized
through the personal idiosyncrasies of such men as the Umayyad prince Khalid b. Yazid, the
‘Abbasid caliph al-Ma’mun (d. 833), and the Persian vizier Ja‘far the
Barmakid (d. 805), who, had acquired more
than a conventional zeal for ancient learning in its Persian, Indian, and Babylonian forms
in general, and its Greek and Hellenistic forms in particular.
The greater translators, most of whom were Syriac-speaking
Christians, of the unorthodox Nestorian and Monophysite communions, were, not mere
translators or servile imitators of Greek or other foreign authors. Some of them, such as
Hunain (d. 873) and Yahia b. ‘Adi (d. 974), are credited with a series of important
scientific and philosophical works. Hunain’s interests seem to have been chiefly
medical and scientific, whereas Yahia seems to have been more interested in theological
and philosophical questions. To a famous pupil of his, Ibn al-Khammar (d. 940), is
ascribed a treatise on the Agreement of the
Opinions of the Philosophers and the Christians, which belongs to the same literary
lineage as the parallel treatise of the Muslim philosophers (such as Ibn Rushd, d. 1198)
who dealt systematically with the questions of reason and revelation in their works.
The works of those early translators were on the whole
compilations which lacked originality. They contained ideas that had been gleaned at
random from the works they had translated. The first genuine philosopher to write in
Arabic was al-Kindi (d. ca. 866), a contemporary of the great Hunain.’Like the rest
of the Arab philosophers and expositors, he differed from the Christian translators in two
important particulars: his religion and his total ignorance of Syriac or Greek, the two
chief languages of the times, besides Arabic. It is surprising that even the greatest
admirers of Greek philosophy such as Averroes, lacked even a perfunctory knowledge of
Greek. The chief reason appears to have been the contempt of the Arabs for all foreign
tongues, which, seems to have spread like an infection, even to non-Arabs of the most
bigoted type. Some philosophers, it is true, chose to write in their native tongues, in
addition to writing in Arabic, as is illustrated by Ibn Sina’s and al-Ghazali’s
Persian writings. This was probably a gesture of nationalist loyalty, not the
manifestation of a genuine desire for a polyglot erudition or distinction.
As a result of their total ignorance of Greek, those
philosophers tended to be less slavish in their interpretation of Greek texts, if a trifle
less exact, than the early Greek commentators, such as Themistius and Alexander. Being
Muslims by faith, they were naturally anxious to justify their interest in the pagan
philosophers of antiquity. Indeed, almost from the beginning it was standard for the
orthodox to reproach all those who “looked into the books of the [Greek]
philosophers”[8] -even presumably when they did not understand them. Such
theological preoccupation was a distinctive feature of the development of Islamic
philosophy. Al-Kindi, the first genuine philosopher, was more than a philosopher with a
theological bent; he was to some extent a theologian with an interest in philosophy. We
might say that al-Kindi still stands on the borderline of philosophy and theology, which the later philosophers tried more boldly,
perhaps, to cross. How far they succeeded in so doing and how far it was possible for them
to span the distance separating Islamic belief from Greek speculative thought will be seen
in later chapters. But it might be mentioned at this stage that al-Kindi’s
theological interests did act as a safeguard against the total submersion of religious
belief in the current of abstract philosophical thought, and the total subordination of
the supernatural light of faith to the light of reason -a devastating temptation which
Islamic philosophy could not ultimately resist. For the subsequent
“illuminationist” trend in the history of Islamic philosophy amounted precisely
to this: the vindication of the right of reason to scale the heights of knowledge unaided
and to lift the veil of mystery which shrouded the innermost recesses of reality. The
ultimate goal of reason, according to Ibn Bajjah, Ibn Rushd, Ibn Tufayl, and others, is
“contact” or “conjunction” (ittisal)
with the universal mind or active intellect, not the enlightenment which the visio Dei promises, by admitting the soul
graciously into the company of the elect, who are blessed with understanding. In this
respect, it is clear that the Islamic philosophers remain true to the Greek ideal, in its
exaltation of man and its faith in his boundless intellectual prowess and his ability to
dispense altogether with any supernatural light.
This is the sense in which Islamic philosophy can be said to
have followed a distinctive line of development which gave it that unity of form which is
a characteristic of the great intellectual movements in history. We should, however, guard
against the illusion that the course of its development was perfectly straight. Some of
the most fascinating Muslim thinkers, such as al-Nazzam (d. 845), al-Razi (d. 925), and
al-Ma‘arri (d. 1057), fall outside the mainstream of thought in Islam. Their
dissident voices lend a discordant note to an otherwise monotonous symphony. The
difficulty of expounding their thought with any degree of completeness is bound up with
its very nonconformist character. Islam did generate such dissentient and solitary souls,
but it could not tolerate or accept them in the end. The historian of Islamic thought
cannot overlook them, however, without distorting the total picture.
Chapter Seven
The Interaction of Philosophy and Dogma
I The Eclipse of Theological Rationalism
As we mentioned earlier, the rise of
Scholastic theology in the middle of the eighth century was the outcome of a new spirit of
inquiry, which the introduction of Greek philosophy in the Muslim world had sparked. In
some cases, however, the interaction of philosophy and dogma resulted in a gradual
cleavage between the two. The systematic philosophers, like al-Farabi and Ibn Sina, tried
hard to lessen the effect of such cleavage by emphasizing the areas of agreement and the
common concerns of philosophy and dogma. Some, such as al-Kindi, went so far as to espouse
the cause of dogma almost unconditionally and sought to erect a compact intellectual
edifice on the foundation of dogma.
A gradual reaction to rationalism in
theology, championed originally by the Mu‘tazilah, was to set in less than a century
after the death of the founder of that school, Wasil b. ‘Ata’. We have already
discussed the role which the great theologian and jurist Ahmad b. Hanbal, as well as the
‘Abbasid caliph al-Mutawakkil, played in the reversal of the pro-Mu‘tazilite
policies of al-Ma’mun in the middle of the ninth century.[1] However, the theological influence of
the Mu’tazilah did not cease altogether as a result of al-Mutawakkil’s policy of
repression. Despite the virtual triumph of the Hanbali and Traditionist party, the spirit
of theological inquiry was not completely snuffed out. In its pure form, the primitive
traditionalism of the early jurists and exegetes was gone forever. The new Traditionism or
orthodoxy was a qualified one that stemmed from the Mu‘tazilite movement itself. Its
rise is associated with the name of Abu’l Hasan al-Ash‘ari (d.935), who,
according to the traditional account, studied theology with al-Juba’i, head of the
Basra branch of the Mu‘tazilite school but broke away from that school at the age of
forty.[2] The Prophet appeared to him in a dream
and urged him to “take charge” of the Muslim community, whereupon
al-Ash‘ari ascended the pulpit at the mosque of Basra and proclaimed his recantation
and his determination to make public “the scandals and follies” of the
Mu‘tazilah.
A debate with his master,
al-juba’i, concerning God’s justice and man’s worthiness brings out vividly
his original anti-Mu‘tazilite sympathies.[3] Whether historical or not, this debate
is significant in so far as it illustrates one of the cardinal issues on which
al-Ash‘ari broke with the Mu‘tazilah. The pupil asks his master: What will be
the fate in the after-life of three brothers, one of whom dies in a state of grace, one in
a state of sin, and one in a state of innocence (i.e., before he comes of age)? The
righteous brother, answers al-juba’i, will be consigned to paradise, the sinner to
hell, and the third to an intermediate position.[4] Al-Ash‘ari then asks: What if the
third brother were to ask to be allowed to join his more fortunate brother? This
privilege, replies al-juba’i, would be denied him on the ground that the first
brother was admitted to paradise on the strength of his good works. If the third brother
were to protest that if he had been given a long life he would have lived righteously, God
would have replied: I foresaw that you would not and therefore chose to spare you
everlasting damnation in hell. At this, the brother Who had died in sin exclaims: Surely,
Lord, you foresaw my own plight, as well. Why, then, did you not deal with me as
mercifully as you have dealt with my other brother?
We are told that al-juba’i was
unable to say what God’s possible answer to such protestations might be, on the
Mu‘tazilite assumption of the unqualified justice of God. The corollaries drawn by
al-Ash‘ari constitute the substance of his view of God’s absolute omnipotence
and sovereignty in the world and the finality of his moral and religious decrees. These
decrees are entirely independent of any conditions, moral or other, apart from God’s
absolute fiat. To Him it belongs to order human life as He pleases, and to the
“servant” to obey without question. Contrary to the contention of the
Mu‘tazilah, the human agent plays no part in the drama of choosing or doing and reaps
none of the moral or religious fruits accruing from such initiative. In their desire to
stress man’s moral freedom and responsibility, the Mu‘tazilah had described him,
somewhat extravagantly, as “the creator of his deeds.” To al-Ash‘ari, such
blasphemous language was tantamount to the denial of God’s uniqueness as the sole
Creator and Sovereign of the world, and consequently implied the recognition of two
creators, in the manner of the Manichaeans (Majus).[5]
The vindication of God’s
absolute power and sovereignty in the world had certain moral implications, which
al-Ash‘ari was quick to draw. To deny man’s role in the drama of moral action
and decision and to impute the responsibility for his deeds and volitions to God involved
the repudiation of God’s justice. However, the claim that man’s deeds are the
result of God’s “decree and preordination” did not necessarily imply,
according to him, the nullification of His justice. Injustice can only denote the
transgression of what has been prescribed by a superior, or the perpetration of what falls
outside the domain of the doer. In both cases, injustice cannot be imputed to God, Who is
the undisputed master and lawgiver of the universe and Who owes no allegiance to anyone
whatsoever.[6]
On the question of the attributes of
God and the creation of the Qur’an, the position of
al-Ash‘ari was equally at variance with that of his Mu‘tazilite master, on the
one hand, and that of the crude anthropomorphists or literalists, on the other. Moved by
the desire to retain the Concept of the full-blooded Creator-God of the Qur’an, he opposed the Mu‘tazilite tendency to divest
God of His positive attributes, and argued, according to a twelfth-century historiographer
and fellow-Ash‘arite, al-Shahrastani, that the essential divine attributes of
knowledge, power, and life are eternal and subsist in God’s essence.[7] They cannot, however, be said to be
either identical with this essence, as the Mu‘tazilah claimed, or not identical with
it. For this would mean that God’s knowledge, power, or life is the same as God, So
that one could address one’s petitions to God’s knowledge, power, or life
instead of to God Himself,[8] which is absurd.
The rationalization of the inherence
of the attributes in God which the Mu‘tazilah attempted is not fully worked out by
al-Ash’ari or his followers. How these
attributes are to be distinguished from God’s essence, in which they inhere and yet
introduce no plurality into it, al-Ash’ari just refused to say. In this respect he is
content to revert to the position of the early Traditionists, such as Malik b. Anas, who
is reported to have argued, in the matter of God’s “sitting upon the
throne,” that the “sitting is known, whereas its mode is unknown. Belief in its
truth is a duty, and its questioning a heresy .”[9]
In his polemical works, however,
al-Ash’ari is as concerned to refute the views of the “negators of the
attributes,” i.e., the Mu‘tazilah, as he is to refute the position of the
literalists and anthropomorphists. In their deference to Scripture, the latter had gone so
far as to attribute corporeity to God, chiefly on the grounds that the text of the Qur’an undeniably stipulated it. Thus Qur’an 75:22-23 speak of the ability of the faithful to
perceive God on the Last Day, and 7:54, and 20:5 speak of His sitting upon the throne. The
anthropomorphists, such as Hisham b. al-Hakam, ‘Abdullah b. Karram, and their
followers in the ninth century, had not hesitated to draw from such Qur’anic passages their full logical consequences and to
conceive of God, as Ibn Rushd will say later, simply as an “eternal man” endowed
with gross corporeal qualities.
The use of logical argument in
matters of theology , and its permissibility, Should first be justified satisfactorily,
however. Al-Ash‘ari’s position, though reactionary by the standards of the
philosophers and thoroughgoing rationalists, is certainly nuancé. Against the literalists and
Traditionists, who questioned the permissibility of deduction or analogy, al-Ash’ari
invokes the authority of the Qur’an, which recognizes
the principle of analogy and employs it effectively in numerous passages.[10] In a tract devoted to the systematic
discussion of this question and entitled Vindication
of the Use of Theological Proof (Kalam), this ex-Mu‘tazilite doctor’s
anti-Traditionist views on an issue which split the ranks of tenth-century theologians are
clearly exhibited. The use of analogy, as indeed the whole method of dialectic or
deduction, is repudiated by the Traditionists on the ground that the Prophet, who had
dealt with every aspect of religion or morals essential to salvation, has not touched on
the question of dialectic (Kalam)
at all. Hence recourse to it constitutes an heretical departure (bid‘ah) from
what is traditionally and authoritatively received.
This argument from silence is
artfully turned by al-Ash‘ari against the Traditionists, who, by the same token, are
just as heretical themselves, since their claim has no basis in the pronouncements or
sayings of the Prophet either. More important still is the fact that the Prophet was fully
conversant with the questions of motion and rest, accident and body, divine attributes,
and so on, with which theology is concerned. However, they are referred to in the
Traditions and the Qur’an in general terms only, and
it is on such references that the whole of theology is based.[11]
Finally, the silence of the Qur’an and the Traditions on those questions that were
subsequently dealt with by the theologians or the jurists is easily justified. The Muslim
community was not faced with the difficulties or doubts which eventually led to them, or
else the Prophet would have laid down explicitly the principles for solving them. As a
result, the jurists and theologians in attempting to solve them had no other recourse than
to draw analogies with what was explicitly laid down in Scripture. For it is the duty of
every “reasonable Muslim” in such matters, al-Ash‘ari argues, “to
refer them to the body of principles consecrated by reason, sense-experience, and common
sense.”[12]
In applying this qualified
rationalism to the cardinal questions debated in theological circles at the time,
al-Ash‘ari, though in fundamental disagreement with the Mu‘tazilah, is
nonetheless anxious to justify his opposition to them on rational grounds. The result is
that his method is analogous to that of the Mu‘tazilah, whereas his doctrine is
substantially a restatement of Traditionist or Hanbali theses.
If we take the Mu‘tazilite
concept of free will as an instance, this dichotomy is clearly brought out. In the Ibanah,
al-Ash‘ari describes the arbitrary power of God in terms that leave hardly any scope
for human initiative:
We believe that Allah
has created everything, by simply bidding it: Be, as He says [in Qur’an
16:42]: “Verily, when we will a thing, our only utterance is: ‘Be’ and it
is”; and that there is nothing good or evil on earth, except what Allah has preordained. We hold that everything is through Allah’s will and that no one can do a thing before he
actually does it, or do it without Allah’s assistance,
or escape Allah’s knowledge. We hold that there is no
Creator but Allah, and that the deeds of the creature are
created and preordained by Allah, as He said [in Qur’an 37:94]: “He has created you and what you
make” ...we hold that Allah helps the faithful to obey
Him, favours them, is gracious to them, reforms and guides them; whereas He has led the
unfaithful astray, did not guide or favor them with signs, as the impious heretics claim.
However, were He to favor and reform them, they would have been righteous, and had He
guided them they would have been rightly guided. ...But it was His will that they should
be ungodly [singular: kafir],
as He foresaw. Accordingly He abandoned them and sealed their hearts. We believe that good
and evil are the outcome of Allah’s decree and
preordination [qada’
wa qadar]: good or evil, sweet or bitter, and we know that what has missed us
could not have hit us, or what has hit us could not have missed us, and that creatures are
unable to profit or injure themselves, without Allah.[13]
In this vindication of the
omnipotence of God and the powerlessness of the creatures al-Ash‘ari simply reaffirms
the Qur’anic Concept of the God-Despot, whose decrees
are both irreversible and inscrutable. At the back of this polemic, however, is the view
of the Mu‘tazilah that man is the “creator of his deeds,” and consequently
a fully free and responsible agent. The Concept of a co-creator with God, according to
al-Ash‘ari, amounts to polytheism and involves a radical curtailing of God’s
absolute power. Despite these strictures, he does not concur with the Traditionists in
their claim that man does not play any part whatsoever in the drama of moral activity. In
his doctrine: of al-kasb,
or acquisition of the merit or demerit for the deed done, al-Ash‘ari seeks a way out
of the moral dilemma of responsibility, without sacrificing the omnipotence of God.
Voluntary actions, in his view, are created by God, but acquired by the human agent or
imputed to him. Creation differs from acquisition in that the former is the outcome of
“eternal power,” whereas the latter is the outcome of the “created
power” of the agent, So that the same action is said to be created by the one and
acquired by the other. Stated differently, man acquires the credit or discredit for the
deed created by God, since it is impossible that God should acquire it in time, while He
is its author eternally.[14] In this subtle verbal distinction
between what is acquired in time and what is created or predestined eternally, lies
according to al-Ash‘ari, the distinction between voluntary and involuntary action,
and also that between the merit or demerit which attaches to the latter. Man, as the locus
or bearer of “acquired” action, becomes responsible for such action, whereas for
involuntary action, such as trembling or falling, etc., he is totally irresponsible. The
fundamental relation between the two forms of action, according to al-Ash‘ari and his
followers, is that man is intuitively conscious of the difference between the one action
and the other.Thus, rather than restore to man the freedom of which the extreme
determinists (al-Jabriyah)
had robbed him, al-Ash‘ari is content restore to him the consciousness of his
subjection to the “eternal power.” Through this subtle distinction, the
predestinarian presuppositions of the Traditionists and determinists are not repudiated,
but their linguistic sting is removed without surrendering the substance of the
predestinarian thesis. The elaboration of this peculiar ethical position, as well as the
occasionalist world-view on which it rested, should perhaps be left to a subsequent
section, because of the part which the successors of al-Ash‘ari played in developing
or refining it.
The historical significance of
al-Ash‘ari’s “reform” lies not in the elaborateness of his solutions
of the theological problems raised by the Mu‘tazilah, but rather in his willingness
to exploit their dialectical method, and, ipso
facto, to moderate the claims of the Traditionists and antirationalists to whom he was
temperamentally drawn. If his theological position, expressed in the classic formula of bila kaifa (ask
not how) must be described as agnostic, it is nonetheless to be clearly distinguished from
the blind agnosticism of the religious bigot who will entertain no questions whatsoever.
For his was the qualified agnosticism of the earnest seeker who ends up by asserting,
rightly or wrongly, the inability of reason to plumb the mystery of man in relation to
God, or of God in relation to man.
II The Ash‘arite school and the Formulation of the Occasionalist Metaphysics of Atoms and accidents
The elaboration of the implication of
al-Ash‘ari’s new theological outlook was left chiefly to his successors in the
tenth and the eleventh centuries. Apart from the substance of their anti-Mu‘tazilite
creed, their attention was now centered on two fundamental questions: (1) the nature and
limits of rational knowledge in relation to religious truth (‘aql AS. Sam‘), and (2) the metaphysical
framework in which the concept of God’s sovereignty and omnipotence should be
expressed. Neither of these questions appears to have been discussed with any thoroughness
by the founder of Ash‘arite movement himself.
The first major figure in the history
of Ash‘arite school was Abu Bakr al-Baqalani (d. 1013), who belongs to the second
generation of Ash‘arite doctors. This theologian, who is credited by later authors
with refining the methods of Kalam,[15] gives in his al-Tamhid the
first systematic statement of the Ash‘arite doctrine and its metaphysical framework.
The book opens with a discussion of
the nature of knowledge or science (‘ilm), in a manner which sets the pattern
for similar Ash‘arite treatises such as al-Baghdadi’s Usul al-Din and
al-Juwayni’s al-Irshad, but it has a distinctly modern ring. Thus, ‘ilm is defined
by the author as “the knowledge of the object, as it really is.”[16] The object in question is then shown
to include both that which is and that which is not (al-ma‘dum), which the Mu‘tazilah but not the
Ash‘arites had declared to be a thing (shay’). Such ‘ilm falls into two major categories: the
eternal knowledge of God and the temporal or created knowledge of creatures capable of
cognition, such as men, angels, jinn, etc. The latter knowledge is subdivided in turn into
necessary (or intuitive) and discursive.
Necessary knowledge is knowledge
which can not be doubted. A subsidiary meaning, however, is that which cannot be dispensed
with i.e. needful.[17] Discursive knowledge, on the hand is
knowledge which is the result of prolonged reflection, or, stated differently, knowledge
which rests on necessary or empirical knowledge.
Such necessary knowledge is acquired
through one or the other of the five senses and is essentially indubitable. However, there
is a type of necessary knowledge which is not a matter of sensation, but is the result of
the immediate apprehension of the mind, for instance man’s knowledge of his own
existence and his inner states or affections, such as pleasure or pain, love or hate,
knowledge or ignorance. To this should also be added the knowledge of the truth or falsity
of indicative statements, as well as the second-intention type of knowledge, such as the
knowledge of what makes shame shameful, fear fearful, etc.[18]
The third type of necessary knowledge
includes, significantly enough, the authoritative accounts of events or facts which are
geographically or historically remote, such a the existence of other countries, of
historical personages, and of ancient kingdoms. To this type of knowledge belongs a
supernatural or extraordinary variety, which God infuses directly into the Soul, without
the help of intermediaries or sense organs, which are the normal channels of this type of
knowledge.[19]
The distinction between rational and
authoritative knowledge was first broached by the Mu‘tazilah,[20] who sought to extend the domain of
reason well into regions which so far had been considered the exclusive preserve of
revelation or faith. The Ash‘arite doctors, as illustrated in al-Baqalani’s
case, recognized the validity of rational knowledge but reacted instinctively against the
Mu‘tazilite infringement on the domain of faith. On two fundamental questions of
“natural theology” and ethics, namely, whether God can be known rationally,
independently of revelation, and whether the knowledge of good and evil is possible prior
to revelation, the Ash‘arite theologians took a qualified anti-Mu‘tazilite
stand. The existence of God and His unity can be known rationally from the consideration
of the createdness (Huduth)
of the world and the logical necessity of a creator (muhdith).
To demonstrate this necessity,
Ash‘arite doctors argued that the world, which they defined as everything other than
God,[21] was composed of atoms and accidents.
Now accidents cannot endure for two successive moments, but are continually created by
God, who produces and annihilates them at will.[22] Similarly, the atoms in which these
accidents inhere are continually created by God and can only endure by virtue of the
accident of duration created in them by God.[23] It
follows from this premise that the world, being created, must necessarily have a creator.[24]
Al-Baqalani’s version of this
argument differs little from the general Ash‘arite argument. He does, however,
strengthen this argument by two others in which the “middle term” is different,
but not the dialectical structure of the reasoning. In the first, he argues that the
priority of certain things in time requires an “agent who made them prior,” who
is God. In the second, he introduces the concept of contingency and argues that things,
considered in themselves, are susceptible of various forms or qualities. The fact that
they actually possess certain forms and no others presupposes a “determinant”
who decrees that they should receive these forms and no others, and this determinant is
God.[25] The last argument, or argument a contingentia mundi, is more fully developed by
later authors, particularly al-Juwayni (d. 1086) in his al-Risalah al-Nizamiyah,
and is the argument which, as we have seen,[26]
Ibn Sina fully exploited in his Metaphysics.
It is noteworthy, however, that the generality of the Ash‘arite theologians showed a
distinct predilection for the argument a novitate
mundi (huduth)
in so far as it harmonized with their concept of a world created in time by an omnipotent
God.[27]
On the other major issue of moral
theology, the distinction between good and evil, the Ash‘arite doctors were equally
in disagreement with the Mu‘tazilah. For, whereas the latter held that man can
determine rationally what is good and evil, prior to revelation, the Ash‘arites
adhered to a strict voluntarist ethics. Good is what God has prescribed, evil what He has
prohibited. In keeping with this voluntarist thesis, they were reluctant to admit that any
merit attached to that type of rational knowledge which is attainable through unaided
reason.[28] God’s power and sovereignty are
such that the very meaning of justice and injustice is bound up with His arbitary decrees.
Apart from those decrees, justice and injustice, good and evil, have no meaning
whatsoever. Thus God is not compelled, as the Mu‘tazilah had argued, to take note of
what is “fitting” in regard to His creatures and to safeguard their moral or
religious interests, so to speak, but is entirely free to punish the innocent and remit
the sins of the wicked. And had He so desired, He could have created a universe entirely
different from the one which He has in fact created, or refrained from creating this
universe or any part of it altogether.[29]
The metaphysical implementation of
the theological and ethical outlook we have just outlined was the other major
philosophical task the Ash‘arite school set itself. In this regard the differences
between its major representatives, from al-Baqalani to al-Shahrastani, are minor.
Al-Baqalani, however, played a pioneering role in elaborating the metaphysical groundwork
of Ash‘arism. Significantly, later authors credit him with the introduction of
atomism, which served as the metaphysical prop of Ash‘arite theology.
The introduction of atomism certainly
antedates the rise of the Ash‘arite school itself, despite the statement of Ibn
Khaldun that al-Baqalani was responsible for the “introduction of the rational
premises on which proofs or theories depend, such as the existence of atoms, the void, and
the proposition that an accident does not inhere in another accident or endure for two
moments.”[30] From the accounts of Islamic atomism
contained in the earliest treatise on Islamic “schisms and heresies,” Maqalat al-Islamiyin,
written by the founder of the Ash‘arite school himself, it appears that atomism had
become firmly established in theological circles by the middle of the ninth century. Thus
Dirar b. ‘Amr, a contemporary of wasil b. ‘Ata’ (d. 748) and one of the
earliest Mu’tazilite doctors of Basra, seems to have been the first theologian to
challenge the generally accepted dualism of substance and accident. Al-Ash‘ari
reports that Dirar held that “body is an aggregate of accidents, which once
constituted, becomes the bearer of accidents.”[31] Similarly a thoroughgoing Shi’ite
materialist who professed an anthropomorphic view of God of the crudest type, Hisham b.
al-Hakam, challenged, as we have seen,[32] this orthodox dualism and reduced
everything to the notion of body, which according to him was divisible ad infinitum[33] and consequently was not made up of
atoms.
By the ninth century, the atomic
theory of Kalam began to take definite shape. From al-Ash‘ari’s account, we can
infer that Abu’l-Hudhail (d. 841 or 849), al-Iskafi (d. 854-855), al-Juba’i (d.
915), al-Ash‘ari’s own master, Mu‘ammar, a contemporary of
Abu’l-Hudhail, as well as two contemporaries of his, Hisham al-Fuwati and ’Abbad
b. Sulayman, accepted the atomic theory in one form or another.[34] To take al-Juba’i as an instance,
this doctor defined substance or the atom as the bearer or substratum of accidents, which,
he added, “was such in itself, and can be conceived as substance prior to its
coming-to-be,”[35] presumably in some disembodied
Platonic state.
The metaphysical speculation on
substance and accident, initiated by the Mu‘tazilah in the eighth century, was
continued and refined by post-Mu‘tazilite doctors. The Ash‘arites, engrossed as
they were with God’s omnipotence and sovereignty in the world, found in atomism a
convenient device for bolstering their theological claims. An Aristotelian world-view,
dominated by causal processes that unfolded themselves almost mechanically, was ill-suited
to their declared purpose of affirming God’s prerogative to act freely and
imperiously in the world. A collocation of atoms which depended, like the accidents
inhering in them, on God’s good pleasure, both for their creation and their duration,
was more compatible in their view with the notion of God’s arbitrary power .
Against the negators of the
accidents, these doctors urged that the motion of a body subsequent to its rest is either
due to the body itself or to something other than the body. The first alternative is
absurd, since the body remains the same throughout the two successive states of motion and
rest. Consequently it can only be due to something other than the body, which we call the
accident.[36] Similarly, the existence of a number
of strokes inflicted by an agent on a patient, for instance, is distinct from the agent,
the patient, or the instrument of striking. Therefore, the number of strokes is something
distinct from all those factors, and that is what we understand by accident.
The number of the accidents which the
orthodox recognized totals thirty. In a general way, they may be divided into primary and
secondary accidents, depending on whether they accompany substance necessarily or not. The
first of the primary accidents are the essential modi
or states (singular: kaun)
such as motion, rest, composition, location. Then come the accidents of color, heat, cold,
etc.[37] Al-Ash‘ari is reported by
al-Baghdadi as holding that eight of the accidents accompany substance necessarily:
motion, color, taste, smell, heat or its
opposite, dampness or its opposite, life or its opposite, and finally duration.[38]
The most peculiar variations on the
theme of accidents are ascribed to Mu‘tazilite and Ash‘aite doctors. Thus the
Mu‘tazilite al-Ka‘bi and his followers are said to have held thlat substance can
be divested of all these “primary accidents” save color; and Abu Hashim,
al-Juba’i’s son, held that upon its coming into being, an atom can be divested
of all accidents save the accident of being (kaun). Another Mu‘tazilite, al-Salihi, went a step
further and argued that an atom could exist without any accidents whatsoever .[39]
It is characteristic of these
accidents, as al-Baghdadi relates, that they are not susceptible by themselves of any
composition, contact, or transmission, since these are characteristics of the body alone.
In this regard they were obviously analogous to the atoms, which were said by some
theologians to be incapable by themselves of any composition, contact, or motion. However,
the two are distinguished somehow, but theoretical difficulties persisted. Thus the
Ash‘arite and, to some extent, the Mu‘tazilite doctors found the phenomena of
motion quite baffling, and they resorted to the most far-fetched devices in attempting to
explain motion rationally. Al-Nazzam, for instance, reduced every accident or quality,
including human actions, to the universal category of motion, and even explained rest as a
“motion of intention.”[40] Therefore, he argued, when a body is
said to be static at a certain point, this can only mean that it had “moved in it
twice.” To account for the possibility of covering a certain distance, which
consisted to him of an infinite number of points or particles, al-Nazzam introduced the
concept of the leap (tafrah),
or the view that a body could move from point A to point C without passing by the
intermediary point B[41]
The Ash‘arites, who subscribed
to an even more extreme concept of discontinuous or discrete being, solved the difficulty
in another way. They argued that motion and rest are two primary states or modi of substance, as has been noted. A substance
which moves from one point to the other is at rest in relation to the second point, but in
motion in relation to the first. Only al-Qalanisi, a somewhat dissident Ash‘arite, is
reported by al-Baghdadi as holding that rest consisted of two successive states of being
in the same place, whereas motion consisted of two successive states in the first and the
second places necessarily [42]
The most characteristic feature of
the atoms of Kalam,
as we have seen,[43] was their perishable nature, which the
Ash‘arites adhered to almost without exception. Not only al-Baqillani but the founder
of the Ash‘arite school himself believed the accidents to be perishable by nature and
to belong to the class of “transient things” (a‘rad) of
this world, referred to in the Qur’an (8:67 and 46:24)[44]
In demonstrating the perishability of
accidents, al-Baghdadi argues that the “thesis of the durability of accidents entails
their indestructibility. For if an accident is said to endure by itself…then it could
persist in being until an opposite, necessitating its destruction, should come into being.
However, there is no sufficient reason why such an opposite should arise and thereby
counter its tendency to resist such an incursion.”[45]
Thus the duration of substances was
made contingent upon the inherence in them of the accident of duration (baqa’). Since,
however, this accident is not capable of duration per se, it followed that either the
durability of substance is to be referred to other accidents of duration indefinitely, or
else another principle of durability had to be introduced. This principle the
Ash‘arites identified with God’s own decree to preserve in being or destroy at
will the atoms or ultimate components of physical objects in the world. Both the accidents
and the atoms in which they inhere depended for their duration in this way on God’s
decree to repeat the process of their recreation as long as He pleased. Notwithstanding
this circumstance, some Ash‘arite doctors found it necessary to give a rational
account of a body’s eventual corruption or annihilation. Thus al-Baqillani described
annihilation (fana’)
as the act of withholding the two accidents of color and mode (kaun) from the
body. Inasmuch as a body can never be divested of these two accidents, such an action
necessarily entailed, according to him, the annihilation of the body.[46] Such annihilation did not depend
therefore on the inherence of the accident of corruption in the body, a thesis which,
despite its strangeness, had at least one exponent. Al-Qalanisi argued that when God
wishes to destroy a certain body, He creates in it
the accident of corruption, which results in its destruction forthwith.[47]
The contribution of late
Ash‘arite doctors, such as al-Juwayni and al-Shahrastani, consists chiefly in
elaborating or defending the concepts and methods to which the school as a whole was
committed. The former, known also as Imam al-Haramayn, developed some of the
epistemological and theological implications of Ash‘arite doctrine in al-Shamil, of
which an abridgement, al-Irshad,
was made by the author. Al-Shahrastani, an author of encyclopedic learning, wrote one of
the best known and most comprehensive “heresiographies” in Arabic, K. al-Milal wa’l-Nihal.
The second part of it is an invaluable source for the reconstruction of the Islamic
picture of Greek philosophy. In addition, al-Shahrastani wrote a compendium of theology, Nihayat al-Iqdam,
which surpasses many of the earlier treatises in its thoroughness and logical coherence,
although it adds little to our knowledge of the scholastic tradition in theology .
III The Systematic Refutation of Neo-Platonism: Al-Ghazali
The greatest figure in the history of
the Islamic reaction to Neo-Platonism is al-Ghazali, jurist, theologian, philosopher, and
mystic. Born in Tus (Khurasan) in 1058, al-Ghazali addressed himself at an early age to
the study of jurisprudence (fiqh) with a certain Radhkani, then moved on toJurjan,
where he continued his studies with Abu’l-Qasim al-Isma’ili. His greatest
teacher, however, was al-Juwayni, the outstanding Ash‘arite theologian of the period.
Al-Juwayni initiated his brilliant pupil into the study of Kalam, philosophy,
and logic. His introduction to the theory and practice of mysticism was due to al-Farmadhi
(d. 1084), a renowned Sufi
of the period.
Al-Ghazali’s fortunes took a
decisive turn as a result of meeting Nizam al-Mulk, vizier of the Saljuk sultan Malikshah.
This able but doctrinaire vizier was fired by an intense zeal for the defense of Sunnite
orthodoxy, and he consequently attacked the Shi‘ite (Isma‘ili)
heterodoxy of the rival Fatimid caliphate at Cairo. The latter had so successfully wielded
the double weapon of propaganda and political assassination throughout the Muslim world
that the Saljuks felt compelled to reply in kind. To this end, Nizam al-Mulk set up a
series of theological schools or seminaries, named after him, throughout the eastern part
of the empire, where the study of Shafi’i fiqh and
Ash‘arite theology were actively pursued. Al-Juwayni had been the head of the
Nizamiyah of Nishapur until his death in 1085. It now devolved upon his disciple to Serve
the cause of Sunnite orthodoxy.[48]
For five years (1091 to 1095), then,
al-Ghazali, as head of the Nizamiyah of Baghdad, pursued his teaching in jurisprudence and
theology with great success. The troubled political situation of the times and the violent
death of Nizam al-Mulk in 1092 at the hand of an Isma’ili assassin, followed shortly
after by the death of the sultan Malikshah, appear to have contributed to his gradual
disillusionment with teaching. His initiation into the practice of the Sufi way, between 1093 and 1094, no doubt added to
his sense of the futility of a career that was not dedicated to the disinterested quest of
truth or the service of God.
In a moving autobiographical work, al-Munqidh, which
has been compared to St. Augustine’s Confessions,
al-Ghazali tells the dramatic story of his spiritual and intellectual anxiety and doubt;
his renunciation, at the height of his fame, of his’ teaching career at Baghdad in
1095; his peregrinations throughout Syria, Palestine, and Hijaz; and his eventual
resumption of teaching, eleven years later, at Nishapur.[49] This second term of instruction,
however, was short lived. Five years later, in 1111, his eventful and active life as a
scholar and mystic came to an untimely end.
Al-Ghazali’s autobiography
introduces us, almost from the very first line, to the intellectual and spiritual problems
with which he had to contend throughout his whole life, and particularly during the period
of tribulation which followed his resignation from the Nizamiyah school at Baghdad. Even
before he was twenty, al-Ghazali tells us, he had been seized by an ardent desire for
truth and had been distressed at the spectacle or conflicting beliefs and creeds and the
passivity and credulity of the common run of mankind who defer blindly to the authority of
their elders. Accordingly, he resolved to search for “certain knowledge,” which
he defines as “that knowledge in which the object is known in a manner which is not
open to doubt at all,”[50] so that if its truth were to be
challenged by a miracle-maker, it would withstand that challenge. When he proceeded to
inquire whether he was actually in possession of such knowledge, he was led to conclude
that the only knowledge which tallied with this description was sense knowledge and the
knowledge of self-evident propositions. In order to pursue the process of doubt to its
logical consequence, however, he felt he had to satisfy himself that such knowledge was
indeed certain. At the end of a painful process of doubt, he found that in fact it was
not. For, in the case of the former, our senses often judge that the object is such and
such, but their judgment is soon subverted by reason. For instance, we look at a shadow
and infer that it is stationary, but soon after we are compelled to admit that it was not.
Or we look at a remote object, such as the planet, which appears to our senses to be the
size of a coin, whereas astronomical evidence compels us to believe that it is many times
larger than the earth.[51]
If sense experience is not to be
trusted, then by analogy the knowledge of necessary propositions or axioms is not to be
trusted either. For, as the senses at once reminded al-Ghazali: What right had he to think
that his confidence in the necessary propositions of reason differed from his confidence
in sensible knowledge? The latter had been shown by reason to be doubtful; might it not
then be that there “exists beyond reason a higher authority, which would, upon its
manifestation, show the judgment of reason to be invalid, just as the authority of reason
had shown the judgment of sense to be invalid?”[52] The analogy of dream is instructive
here. Very often in dreams we are confident of the reality of our experiences but this
confidence is dispelled as soon as we wake up. Might it not be, then, that our waking life
is no better, as the Prophet has said, than dreaming, in comparison with the life after
death?
These doubts, al-Ghazali tells us,
continued to afflict him like a real sickness for almost two months. Eventually he
recovered his intellectual health, not through his own efforts, but rather through a
“light which God infused into his heart, which indeed is the key to most species of
knowledge.”[53] This light, he now realized, was not a
matter of discourse or argument, but of divine grace, which the Prophet had described as
“the dilation of the heart, whereby it becomes prone to the reception of Islam.”[54] The signs attendant upon it are the
renunciation of this world of illusion and the turning toward the world of reality.
Much has been written about
al-Ghazali’s sincerity and the significance of his use of the method of doubt.
Whether or not the account given in al-Munqidh is a factual record of his spiritual and
intellectual experience is a purely academic question. What is of particular significance
is the profound earnestness with which he depicts in this work the “states of his own
soul” as it was assailed by doubt, recovered faith through the outpouring of divine
light, and how finally he consented to champion publicly the cause of orthodoxy against
the sectarians of heresy and deceit.
Of these sectarians he singles out
four groups that might be presumed to be in possession of the (Islamic) truth in the
eleventh century; if none of them was in possession of such truth, the quest for certainty
would be entirely futile. These four are the theologians, the Isma’ilis (or Batinis),
the philosophers, and the Sufis.
The aim of theology (Kalam), which he
had first studied, was the defense of orthodoxy and the repulsion of the heretics’
attacks on it. In this defense, the theologians start with some premises that are not
certain in themselves but must be accepted on the authority of Scripture or the Consensus
of the community. Hence, this branch of learning, though useful, does not lead per se to
that indubitable certainty which al-Ghazali was seeking.[55]
The Isma’ili doctrine, known as Ta‘lim (instruction) during this period, did
not quench his thirst for truth either; For the substance of Isma’ili doctrine is
that the knowledge of truth is not possible without a teacher, and the only teacher whose
teaching cannot be doubted is an infallible teacher, or, as he was called by the
Isma’ilis, the Imam.
Here, however, the question arises: What are the marks of such an infallible Imam and where is
he to be found? Muslims have an infallible teacher, namely, the Prophet. The
Isma’ilis Who recognize the authority of the Prophet argue nevertheless that he is
dead. In reply to this argument it can be urged that the Imam, though not
dead, is equally inaccessible, since he is said to be m temporary concealment(gha’ib).[56]
Despite the vehemence with which
al-Ghazali inveighs against the Isma’ilis and their splinter groups in his works,[57] his polemics against the Arab
Neo-Platonists are by far the most sustained and the most searching. And it is naturally
these polemics that are particularly interesting to us here. The suppressed, almost
instinctive, reaction against rationalism in general and Greek philosophy in particular,
which had been a characteristic mark of orthodoxy heretofore, bursts forth in
al-Ghazali’s attacks on the Muslim Neo-Platonists, particularly al-Farabi and Ibn
Sina. Earlier orthodox writers had been content to challenge rationalism or to reproach
the philosophically inclined, on grounds either of piety or of xenophobia. Al-Ghazali, who
agreed with the general sentiment of the orthodox, felt nonetheless that “only one
who has mastered the science [of philosophy] to such a degree that he can vie with the
most proficient in that science”[58] and even excel them will be qualified
to show the incoherence of their doctrine. Since no one had accomplished this difficult
task before him, al-Ghazali felt compelled to grapple with this problem with all his
might. He therefore turned to the study of philosophy in his spare time, since he was
occupied during this period with teaching religious subjects to no fewer than 300 students
at the Nizamiyah of Baghdad. Although he does not mention this in his autobiography, he
had, as we have seen, already made a start in that direction as a student of al-Juwayni in
Nishapur.[59] Presumably, his study of philosophy in
a systematic way was made during this second period. In three years, he was able,
according to his own account, “through God’s assistance,” to master the
philosophical sciences completely. The fruit of these years of philosophical initiation
was a work entitled the Intentions of the
Philosophers, in which he states that his express purpose is to expound the doctrines
of the philosophers, as a prelude to refuting them in a subsequent work.[60] This exposition of the tenets of Arab
Neo-Platonism is so skillfully written that a careless reader would conclude that it is
the work of a conventional Neo-Platonist, as indeed the thirteenth-century Scholastic
doctors had concluded when it appeared in the Latin version of Dominicus Gundissalinus,
entitled Logica et Philosophia Algazelis Arabis.
The circumstance was at the root of the widspread belief in the later Middle Ages that
Algazel was a genuine Neo-Platoinist of the stamp of Avicenna and others.[61]
Other fruits of al-Gazali’s
philosophical intition are to be found in an important manual of Aristotelian logic, Mi’yar al-’Ilm
(The criterion of Science). This work, and the Intentions and Tahafut, form a
philosophical trilogy of the utmost significance for the study of history of the struggle
between the theologians and the philosophers of Islam.
We are not, however, concerned here
with al-Ghazali’s contribution to the dissemination of Neo-Platonism, since his
professed aim was not its advancement but rather its rebuttal. Indeed, al-Farabi and Ibn
Sina, the two major targets of his attack, had by thoroughness rendered any further
creative contribution in that domain almost impossible. The chief contribution of
al-Ghazali lay instead in his identification with the antiphilosophical party, and his
attempt to prove the incoherence of the philosophers on philosophical grounds; hence his importance in
the history of philosophical thought in Islam.
Al-Ghazali’s motive in writing his Tahafut (or Collapse
of the Philosophers) is stated explicitly to be religious. What prompted him write
this work, he tells us, was the way in which as small group of free-thinkers had been led
to repudiate Islamic Beliefs and neglect the ritual basis of worship as unworthy of their
intellectual attainments. They were confirmed in this by the widespread adulation reserved
for ancient philosophers, from Socrates to Aristotle, who were erroneously supposed to
partake of their irreligion. However, had they taken the trouble to examine the teaching
of those philosophers, they would have discovered that “every one worthy of note
among the ancients and the moderns”[62] subscribed to the fundamentals of
religious belief, i.e. the existence of God and the reality of the Day of judgement.
Differences among them affect only incidentally the substance of their belief.
In substantiating the latter claim,
al-Ghazali draws a distinction between those philosophical sciences such as mathematics
and logic, which are completely innocuous from a religious point of view, and those which,
like physics and metaphysics, contain the bulk of the heresies or errors of the
philosophers.[63] Three of those philosophers deserve
special mention: Aristotle, who organized and perfected the philosophical sciences; and
al-Farabi and Ibn Sina, who are the two most authoritative and trustworthy expositors of
Aristotelian philosophy in Islam.[64] The rebuttal of the view of these
three should enable the critic of philosophy to dispense with the rebuttal of lesser
figures.
Al-Ghazali’s attack is thus
judiciously leveled at the two leading Muslim Neo-Platonists directly, and indirectly at
Aristotle, their master. Altogether, he enumerates sixteen metaphysical and four physical
propositions that have an obvious religious relevance and against which the unguarded
believer must be warned. Of these propositions, three are particularly obnoxious from a
religious point of view, and consequently those who uphold them must be declared
renegades, liable to the religious sanctions against renegades in Islam. These
propositions are the eternity of the world a parte ante, God’s knowledge of universals
only, and the denial of the resurrection of the body.[65] The remaining seventeen propositions
do not, in al-Ghazali’s opinion, justify the charge of irreligion (kufr), but simply
that of heresy (bid‘ah).
Many of them are professed by other sectarians of Muslim heresay, such as the
Mu‘tazilah, and should not on that account be regarded as equivalent to apostasy
except on a very narrow-minded or bigoted interpretation, which al-Ghazali is careful to
disallow.
The first proposition of the Tahafut bears on
the eternity of the world as professed by the Islamic Neo-Platonists and Aristotle. In
their espousal of the emanationist world-view, as we have seen, the latter had
disassociated themselves from the main body of orthodox Islam. As early as
al-Ash‘ari, the heterodox implications of the thesis of eternity had been clearly
discerned by the theologians, but with the exception of Ibn Hazm[66] (d. 1064) no systematic exposition and
refutation of these implications had been attempted before al-Ghazali’s time.
Implicit in the polemic of the theologians against this thesis is the claim that it
militated against the Qur’anic concept of creation ex nihilo, and as a corollary involved an arbitrary
limitation of God’s absolute power.
The views of the philosophers on the
question of the eternity of the world are stated by al-Ghazali to be three: (1) the view
of the vast majority, ancient and modern, who believed it to be eternal; (2) the view of
Plato, who held that it was created in time;[67] and (3) the view of Galen, who suspend
judgment on this issue.[68]
In his rebuttal of the eternalist
thesis, al-Ghazali asserts that the world was created in time, through an eternal decree
of God. He rejects in this connection the claim that the lapse of time which separates the
eternal decree of God and the creation of the world involves the supposition that God
could not accomplish the creation at once. This claim, he argues, does not rest on any
demonstrative grounds but is simply a dogmatic assertion.[69]
A mathematical argument is then
advance against the Neo-Platonists. The eternity of the world entails logically that an
infinite number of revolutions of the heavens have already elapsed. We know, however, that
these revolutions can serve as the basis of mathematical computations. For instance, the
sphere of the sun completes a single revolution in a year, that of Saturn in 30, that of
Jupiter in 12, and that of the firmament in 36,000 years. A finite ratio between the
revolutions of the sun and the other spheres can be given as follows: 1/30, 1/12, 1/36,000
respectively, which would contradict the assumption that these revolutions are infinite
and occur in an infinite time.[70]
Moreover, these revolutions are
either odd or even, and must consequently be finite. For the infinite is neither odd nor
even, since it can be increased by one indefinitely, while remaining infinite. To top it
all, the Neo-Platonists assert the possibility of an infinite number of Souls, existing in
a disembodied condition, as Ibn Sina held,[71] despite the logical contradiction
which the concept of an actual infinite involves.
In his rebuttal of the Avicennian
arguments that God is prior to the world in essence, rather than in time, al-Ghazali takes
an unequivocal stand in support of the creation of time. When we say that God is prior to
the world, we simply mean, according to him, that God existed while the world was not, and
continued to exist together with the world. What these two propositions assert is the
existence of an entity (God) followed by both entities together.[72] The representation of a tertium quid (time) is a trick of the imagination,
which compels us to represent both entities as linked together, through this tertium quid.
As for the view that prior to its
creation the world was obviously possible, it does not necessarily entail, as the
Neo-Platonists contend, an eternal substratum in which possibility inheres. For, on this
view, not only the possible but its two contraries, the impossible and the necessary,
would also require such a substratum, and this is clearly absurd. The possible, the
impossible, and the necessary, as indeed all other common qualities, have only a
conceptual reality. What exists is simply the entity of which they are predicated.[73]
The second question of the Tahafut deals with perpetuity or eternity, of which
post-eternity is explicitly stated to be a logical this question raise the same crucial
theological issues as that of pre-eternity, of which post-eternity is explicitly stated to
be a logical offshoot. A whole group of questions (3 to 11) deals next with God and His
attributes. In Question 3, the fundamental issue is raised whether, in the context of
Neo-Platonism, God could be rightly described as the Creator or Maker of the world. For,
according to the Neo-Platonists, the world emanates from God (or the First, as they call
Him) necessarily, just as the effect emanates from the cause or the light from the sun.
Now a genuine agent must be conscious and free, so that God can only be designated by
these philosophers as the Maker (Sani‘) of the world metaphorically.
Moreover the world, being eternal,
according to them, can hardly be said to be created. For creation or making denotes the
act of bringing an entity forth into being, out of nothing, and the eternal is forever in
being.[74] Likewise the Neo-Platonists hold that
out of one only one can come (ex uno non fit nisi
unum), but since God is one and the world multiple, there can be no sense in saying
that He is its Maker. Indeed, from their premises it would follow that only a series of
ones or simple entities could emanate from the “First.” As to the multiple or
composite entities which make up the world, none of the arguments of the Neo-Platonists
can account for their production.
What is more, the Neo-Platonists are
unable to prove the existence of God either (Question 4). All their arguments rest on the
impossibility of an infinite egress and the necessity of positing ultimately an Uncaused
Cause of the series of effects. However, (a) bodies are eternal, according to them, and
require, in consequence, no cause, and (b) an infinite series is not impossible since it
follows from their thesis of the eternity of the world that an infinite series of effects
has come and gone heretofore. Some of them, as we have seen in the case of Ibn Sina, even
admit that an infinite number of Souls can exist in a disembodied condition.[75]
Al-Ghazali next turns to the question
of divine attributes. The Neo-Platonists are unable prove the unity of God (Question 5).
The substance of their proof is that if we posit two necessary beings, necessity would not
belong to each of them essentially, but through a cause, so that the Necessary Being would
be caused, which is absurd. This proof is not valid because their distinction between the
necessary-in-itself and the necessary-through-a-cause, upon which this proof rest, is
unfounded. The Neo-Platonists, in fact, deny, the divine attributes altogether (Question
6). Such attributes are, according to them, accidents of the essence and, as such, involve
plurality and contingency in the subject, God, they claim, cannot be the bearer often
attributes, but they admit at the same time that He is nonetheless knowing (‘alim), which
obviously implies that He possesses the attribute of knowledge, however we might interpret
it.[76]
The question of divine knowledge is
the second issue on which Al-Ghazali denounces the Neo-Platonists. We might pause
therefore to consider his objections at length. In Question 11 he introduces the
discussion by expounding the Islamic (Ash‘arite) view of divine knowledge, Since the
act of willing implies the knowledge of what is willed, and the whole world has been
willed by God, it follows that the whole world is known to Him and is caused by this
double act of knowing and willing.[77] But to be capable of knowledge and
will is to be alive. Therefore God must be alive and, as such, capable of knowing
everything which emanates from Him, together with Himself, as its source. The
Neo-Platonists, who have stripped God of all essential attributes, have been led to
conclude that “the Lord of Lords and the Cause of Causes has no knowledge whatsoever
of anything which happens in the world. [One might ask them, therefore] what difference is
there between Him and the dead, except in regard of His self-knowledge [ which they
admit], and what excellence does this self-knowledge involve, when coupled with ignorance
of everything else?”[78]
The philosophers, having thus denied
that God has will, are unable to prove that He has knowledge either. The substance of the
argument of Ibn Sina on this score, for instance, is that the First, being entirely
immaterial, must be a pure intellect (‘aql), and must accordingly know all things, since the
only bar to such knowledge is matter.[79] However, Ibn Sina and his fellow
Neo-Platonists are unable to substantiate their claim that God is an intellect, but simply
infer it from the premise that He is not a material entity. However, all that can be
inferred from the proposition that the First is not a material object, nor an accident of
a material object, is that He is self-subsistent. To argue that He is in consequence an
intellect, since He knows Himself or knows other things, is to beg the question. Only on
the assumption that He knows Himself, as well as other things, can it be asserted that He
is a pure intellect, which is precisely the point at issue.[80]
It may be objected that the
philosophers do not deny that the world is the product of God’s action, but only that
He has willed it in time. For they do not question the general proposition that the agent
is necessarily conscious of his action. God, who has produced the “whole,” must
in consequence be conscious of His production.[81]
Al-Ghazali counters this objection on
three grounds. (1) The world is said by the Neo-Platonists to emanate from God by a
“necessity of nature,” analogous to the emanation of light from the sun.
Obviously, such an emanation does not involve either willing or thinking on the part of
the agent. (2) Some (e.g., Ibn Sina) claim that the emanation of the “whole”
from God is the result of His knowledge of this “whole” and this knowledge is
identical with the essence of God. This claim, however, is disputed by other philosophers,
who describe emanation in terms of natural necessity, as in (1) .(3) Even if the latter
version of emanation is accepted, the only corollary thereof is that God knows only the
first entity to result from His action, i.e., the first intellect, which in turn knows
what results from it, and so on down the scale of subsequent emanations. God cannot,
according to this version, know the “whole” either.[82]
Indeed, it does not follow from the
premises of the philosophers that God knows Himself either (Question 12), for we infer the
knowledge of self from the fact of life, which in turn is inferred from knowledge and
will. The philosophers, in denying that God is capable of willing, as we have seen, are
unable to prove that He knows Himself or anything that follows from Him. To be consistent,
the philosophers must deny that God is capable of knowing, seeing, or hearing (attributed
to Him by the generality of Muslims), since these attributes denote, according to them,
imperfections rightly predicated of the creature but not of God.[83]
Perhaps the most crucial aspect of
the problem of divine knowledge, from the Islamic point of view, is the denial of
God’s knowledge of particulars. The Qur’an states
explicitly (e.g., 34:3) that nothing escapes God’s knowledge, not even “the
smallest particle in heaven or on earth.” Philosophers who admit, like Ibn Sina, that
God knows things other than Himself, have argued nevertheless that the mode of His
knowledge is “universal.” It is not subject, like “particular”
knowledge, to the limitations of time or place. Thus God knows an event (say, the eclipse
of the sun) prior to its occurrence or subsequently, in the same instantaneous manner. For
He knows a priori the series of causes from
which it will ultimately result. Similarly, He knows an individual man, for instance Zaid
or Amr, in so far as He knows the “absolute man,” i.e., independently of the
conditions of time or place. The particular or accidental qualities, or the spatiotemporal
determinations, which set such an individual apart from other individuals, are objects of
sense experience of which God cannot possibly partake.[84]
In his rebuttal al-Ghazali argues
that God’s knowledge is indeed independent of the conditions of time and space. It
does not, on that account, exclude relation to particulars, which are subject to such
conditions. The changes to which the mode of this knowledge is liable do not involve
change in the essence of the knower, but rather in the relationship of his knowledge to
the object, which is continually changing.
If it is maintained nonetheless that
such relations enter into the definition of the object, so that change in the latter will
involve change in the knower necessarily, one might retort that, if this were true, even
the knowledge of universals would involve change in the knower, in so far as such
knowledge involves different relationships to the knower. And since these universals are
infinite in number, it is not clear how, on the argument of the philosophers, the unity of
God’s knowledge can be safeguarded, unless we assume that the change or plurality in
the object does not necessarily affect the knower.[85]
Nor does it follow from the premises
of the Neo-Platonists that the Eternal Being (God) is not subject to change. They posit
that the world (which according to them is eternal) is nevertheless subject to change. As
to the detraction from the perfection of God which the dependence of His knowledge upon
the changing object must involve, we can only observe that there can be no greater
detraction from this perfection than the claim of the philosophers that everything
emanates from God by way of natural necessity, without His knowledge or preordination.[86]
In the “physical” part of
the Tahafut, al-Ghazali considers two major questions: the repudiation of the necessity of
the causal nexus and the resurrection of the body. The former (Question 17) had been one
of the major issues which more than two centuries earlier had set the theologians against
the philosophers in general and the Peripatetics in particular. The tendency of the latter
to ascribe to “secondary causes” a certain degree of efficacy in the natural
order was frowned upon by the theologians on the ground that it militated against the Qur’anic concept of an omnipotent Deity who carried out His
grand cosmic designs imperiously and directly and who, in consequence, had no need of any
mediator.[87] The occasionalist metaphysics of atoms
and accidents, which as we have seen was developed by the theologians of the ninth
century, was designed precisely to safeguard God’s absolute independence from any
conditions or limitations, natural or other. With the exception of a few Mu‘tazilite
theologians who introduced the concept of generation (tawallud) as a
theoretical device for retaining the efficacy of natural agents,[88] the Muslim theologians rejected
“secondary causation” as incompatible with God’s uniqueness and sovereignty
in the world. Al-Ghazali, however, was the first theologian to undertake a systematic
refutation of the concept of a necessary causal nexus. In this, he appears to have been
influenced by the Greek skeptics of the Pyrrhonian school.[89]
The discussion of causality opens
with the statement that the correlation between the so-called cause and effect is not
necessary, for only where logical implication is involved can a necessary correlation be
admitted. It is plain, however, that between two distinct conditions or events, such as
eating and satiety; contact with fire and burning, decapitation and dying, no such
correlation can be asserted. The observed correlation between concomitant events in
medicine, astronomy, and the arts is due merely to God’s action in joining them
constantly. It is logically possible, however, for this conjunction to be infringed and
the so-called effects be produced ab initio,
without their concomitant causes, as indeed happens in what Muslims universally regard as
miracles.[90]
Take the case of fire in relation to
cotton. The philosophers claim that fire causes the burning of the cotton, whereas we
maintain, says al-Ghazali, that the real agent in this process is God, acting either
directly by Himself, or indirectly through an angel. For fire is inanimate, and cannot
therefore be said to cause anything whatsoever. The only proof that the philosophers can
advance is that we observe burning to occur upon contact with fire, but observation simply
proves that the burning follows upon contact with fire, not that it is due to it, or that
it is in fact the only possible cause of burning.
Or take the case of life and growth,
in relation to the animal. It is plain that life, as well as the cognitive and motive
faculties which inhere in the sperm of the animal, are not the effects of the four primary
qualities.[91] Nor is the father, who deposits the
sperm in the mother’s womb, the cause of the infant’s life, hearing, seeing,
etc. This cause is the First Being. In fact, the major philosophers admit that the
accidents or events which result from the conjunction of natural causes and effects are
ultimately due to the “Giver of Forms,” who is an angel or a separate substance[92] from whom the “substantial
forms” of natural objects emanate, once matter has become sufficiently disposed to
receive them.
However, the philosophers might admit
that the ultimate causes of natural processes are supermundane, and yet ascribe to the
action of natural causes or agents the disposition or aptitude for receiving their action.
Accordingly, if we posit that fire is of a certain nature and cotton is of a certain
nature also, it is impossible that fire should sometimes burn cotton and sometimes not,
unless the nature of fire or that of cotton has changed in the interval.[93]
Al-Ghazali’s solution of this
difficulty is that the supermundane principles or agents, particularly God, do not act by
way of causal necessity, as the philosophers claim, but rather by way of will.
Consequently, it is quite possible logically for God to cause burning in some instances
but not in others. One might object that, on this supposition, everything becomes possible
and nothing will be known with certainty, except where God wished at the same time to
impart directly the knowledge corresponding to the action. For instance, we may imagine a
man looking out on a strange scene: fire burning, lions roaring, soldiers marching,
without beholding any part of it, because God did not create in him the corresponding
perception of this scene at the time. Or we may leave a book behind and, on returning
home, find that the book has changed into a lad or a beast, or the lad has turned into a
dog, etc. God could thus create whatever He pleases, in any order He pleases, since He is
not bound by any order, causal or other .[94]
In his retort, al-Ghazali states that
these absurdities would result only if we assume that God will not create in us the
knowledge corresponding to the events or to the fact that they are possible. But God has
created in us the knowledge that these events are merely possible, not that they are
actual. They could just as well occur as not occur. Their repetitiveness “establishes
firmly, in our minds [the notion] of their occurrence according to the past habitual
course.”[95] But it is possible for a prophet or an
ordinary man with prophetic or acute intuitive powers to foresee that such events will
happen in a manner which does not conform with the normal course of events in nature. In
such situations God simply creates in the mind of the knower the corresponding knowledge
and thereby the alleged difficulty vanishes.
The knowledge of the sequence of such
events is normally dependent on their actual occurrence. Without denying that certain
elements, e.g., fire, are endowed with certain properties, such as the power to burn
cotton, however, it is not logically excluded that God or His angels may cause this power
to be checked in such a way that it will not cause burning in the cotton; or He may create
in the cotton the power to resist the action of burning. Such miracles, reported in the Qur’an, as [Christ’s] resurrecting the dead or
[Moses’] turning a stick into a serpent could thus be explained in a perfectly
rational manner. Or it may be possible for God to effect His miraculous designs without
violence to the natural process of events, but rather through what might be called
telescoping or abridging this process. Thus matter, according to the Peripatetic
philosophers, is susceptible of many contrary qualities. The generation of animals, in
their view, results from a series of permutations culminating in the animal in question.
Earth turns into a vegetable, which upon being consumed by the animal parent turns into
blood, which in turn is converted inside the body into the seminal fluid, which eventually
develops into an individual offspring. Habitually, this process takes a fairly long time,
but it is not logically excluded that God could bring these permutations about in a
shorter period than is His wont, and then in progressively shorter periods until we come
to a period so short as to be instantaneous. And this is what we denote as a miracle.[96]
Indeed the philosophers allow that
the generation of animals or vegetables is bound up with the ability of matter, as it
becomes disposed through the influence of the heavenly conjunctions and their diverse
motions, to receive the forms which emanate from the active intellect or Giver of Forms,
as we have seen. On this supposition, the most extraordinary occurrences in. the world
become possible, and extraordinary events or miracles perfectly intelligible.
The final three “physical”
questions of the Tahfut
deal with the nature of the Soul and its immortality, according to Neo-Platonic doctrine.
In Question 18, al-Ghazali sets forth the arguments of those philosophers for the
immateriality and simplicity of the Soul and shows that they are simply inconclusive. Nor
are their arguments for its immortality conclusive either, for these rest on the
simplicity and the immateriality of the Soul, which they are unable to establish (Question
19).
Since none of these arguments is
conclusive, the only recourse left is the authority of Scripture or revelation (al-shar‘),[97] which asserts immortality in an
undoubted manner and expatiates on the state of the Soul in the after-life. Much of what
the philosophers say concerning the noncorporeal or spiritual pleasures reserved to the
Soul in the after-life is in conformity with the teaching of Scripture. What we question,
al-Ghazali argues, is that their knowledge of the immortality of the Soul and the
spiritual pleasures or pains of the after-life are known through unaided reason, and that
they are the only types of pleasure or pain which man can experience after death. There is
no logical absurdity involved in positing both types of pleasure or pain, i.e., the
spiritual and the bodily, as well as the bodily resurrection laid down in Scripture. The
claim of the philosophers that sensuous pleasures and pains, as depicted in the Qur’an, are no more than allegories intended for the
edification of the masses is very tenuous, and the analogy between the passages in the Qur’an that describe them and the passages that refer to God
in anthropomorphic terms is not a sound analogy. The latter can and ought to be
interpreted allegorically, but not the former. For, whereas it is logically impossible
that God should be described in corporeal terms and as possessing physical members or
occupying space, the bodily rewards and punishments alluded to in the Qur’an are not logically impossible, as has been shown under
the general heading of miracle and the miraculous.[98] God could thus restore the Soul on the
Day of Judgment to a body either identical with or analogous to its original body, and
thereby enable it to partake of both bodily and nonbodily pleasure. In fact, it is with
the possibility of such a dual enjoyment that its complete happiness is bound up.
[1] See for this general
classification of the sciences Ibn Khaldun, al-Muqaddimah, pp. 435f, and al-Farabi,
ihsa’ al-’Ulum, pp. 58f.
[2] Arthur Jeffery,
Materials for the History of the Text of the Qur’an, pp. 1-10.
[3] See Guillaume, The Traditions of Islam, pp. 9ff.
[4] Al-Shahrastani, al-Milal wa’l –Nihal, p.
17 (hereafter cited as al-Milal)
[5] See al-Khayyat, Kitab al-Intisar, p. 21.
[6] Al-Shahrastani, al-Milal, pp. 17 f., and al-Farabi, Ihsa al-‘Ulum, pp. 107 f.
[7] See Wensinck, The Muslim Creed, pp. 63 f.
[8] Al-Milal,
p. 18. See al-Ash‘ari, Maqalat al-Islamiyin,
p. 485.
Tidak ada komentar:
Posting Komentar